Cybersemiotic Pragmaticism and Constructivism
Søren Brier
Log in to download the full text for free
> Citation
> Similar
> References
> Add Comment
Abstract
Context: Radical constructivism claims that we have no final truth criteria for establishing one ontology over another. This leaves us with the question of how we can come to know anything in a viable manner. According to von Glasersfeld, radical constructivism is a theory of knowledge rather than a philosophy of the world in itself because we do not have access to a human-independent world. He considers knowledge as the ordering of experience to cope with situations in a satisfactory way. Problem: Von Foerster and Krippendorff show that the central goal of a constructivist theory of knowing must be to find a way of putting the knower into a known that is constructed so as to keep the knower, as well as the knowing process, viable in practice. Method: The conceptual and philosophical analysis of present theories and their necessary prerequisites suggests that such foundation for viable knowing can be built on the analysis of what the ontological prerequisites are for establishing viable observing, cognition, communication and observer-communicators, and communication media and vehicles. Results: The moment an observer chooses to accept his/her own embodied conscious presence in this world as well as language, he/she must accept other humans as partly independently existing conversation partners; if knowledge and knowing has to make sense, he/she must also accept as prerequisites for our observation and conversation a pre-linguistic reality from which our bodies come and which our conversation is often about. Furthermore, we can no longer claim that there is a reality that we do not know anything about: From being here in conversation, we know that the world can produce more or less stable embodied consciousnesses that can exchange and construct conceptual meanings through embodied conversations and actions that last over time and exist in space-time and mind, and are correlated to our embodied practices. We can also see that our communication works through signs for all living systems as well as in human language, understood as a structured and progressively developed system of communication. The prerequisite for this social semiotic production of meaning is the fourfold “semiotic star of cybersemiotics,” which includes at least four different worlds: our bodies, the combination of society, culture and language, our consciousness, and also an outer nature. Implications: The semiotic star in cybersemiotics claims that the internal subjective, the intersubjective linguistic, our living bodies, and nature are irreducible and equally necessary as epistemological prerequisites for knowing. The viable reality of any of them cannot be denied without self-refuting paradoxes. There is an obvious connectedness between the four worlds, which Peirce called “synechism.” It also points to Peirce’s conclusion that logic and rationality are part of the process of semiosis, and that meaning in the form of semiosis is a fundamental aspect of reality, not just a construction in our heads.
Erratum: The paper erroneously refers to “pleroma.” The correct term is “plemora.”
Key words: ontology, embodiment, philosophy of observing, second-order cybernetics, autopoiesis, semiotics, language, phenomenology, radical constructivism, Edmund Husserl, Charles Sanders Peirce, George Spencer-Brown
Citation
Brier S. (2009) Cybersemiotic pragmaticism and constructivism. Constructivist Foundations 5(1): 19-39. http://constructivist.info/5/1/019
Export article citation data:
Plain Text ·
BibTex ·
EndNote ·
Reference Manager (RIS)
Similar articles
References
Atkin A. (2005) C. S. Peirce’s pragmatism. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved from http://www.iep.utm.edu/peircepr/ on 15 October 2009
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Bateson F. & Bateson M. C. (2005) Angels fear: Towards an epistemology of the sacred. Hampton Press, New Jersey. Originally published in 1987.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Berkeley G. (1948–1957) The works of George Berkeley, bishop of Cloyne. Nine volumes. Edited by A. A. Luce & T. E. Jessop. Thomas Nelson and Sons, London.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Brier S. (2007) Applying Luhmann’s system theory as part of a transdisciplinary frame for communication science. Cybernetics & Human Knowing 14(2–3): 29–65.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Brier S. (2008) A Peircean panentheist scientific mysticism. International Journal of Transpersonal Studies 27: 20–45.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Brier S. (2008) Bateson and Peirce on the pattern that connects and the sacred. In: Hoffmeyer J. (ed.) A legacy for living systems: Gregory Bateson as a precursor for biosemiotic thinking. Biosemiotics 2. Springer, London: 229–255.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Esbjorn-Hargens S. & Zimmerman M. (2009) Integral ecology: Uniting multiple perspectives on the natural world. Integral Books, Boston MA.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Foerster H. von (1979) The cybernetics of cybernetics. In: Krippendorff K. (ed.) Communication and control in society. Gordon and Breach Science Publishers, New York: 5–8.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Foerster H. von (1981) On cybernetics of cybernetics of cybernetics and social theory. In: Roth G. & Schwegler H. (eds.) Self-organizing systems, an interdisciplinary approach. Campus, Frankfurt: 102–105.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Foerster H. von (1984) On self-organizing systems and their environment. In: Observing systems. Intersystems, Seaside CA: 2–23. Originally published in Yovits M. C. & Cameron S. (eds.) (1960) Self-Organizing systems. Pergamon Press, London: 31–50.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Foerster H. von (2003) Ethics and second-order cybernetics. In: Understanding understanding. Springer, New York: 287–304. Originally published in French in: Ray Y. & Prieur B. (eds.) (1991) Système, ethique, perspectives en therapie familiale. ESF editeur, Paris: 41–55.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Guyer P. (1998) Kant, Immanuel. In: Craig E. (ed.) Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy. Routledge, London. Retrieved on October 14, 2009 from http://www.rep.routledge.com/article/DB047SECT5
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Heidegger M. (1995) The fundamental concepts of metaphysics: World, finitude, solitude. Indiana University Press, Indiana.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Hintikke J. (1998) What is abduction? The fundamental problem of contemporary epistemology. Transaction of the Charles S. Peirce Society XXXIV (3): 503–534.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Husserl E. (1931) Ideas: A general introduction to pure phenomenology. Translated by W. R. Boyce Gibson. Humanities Press, New York. Originally published in 1913.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Husserl E. (1970) Logical investigations. 2 Volumes. Translated by J. N. Findlay. Routledge and Kegan Paul: London. Originally published in 1921.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Husserl E. (1997) Fænomonologiens idé. Hans Reitzels Forlag, Copenhagen. English translation: (1999) The idea of phenomenology. Husserliana: Edmund Husserl Collected Works Volume 8. Translated by L. Hardy. Kluwer, Dordrecht.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Husserl E. (1999) Cartesianske meditationer, Hans Reitzels forlag, København. Translated from Husserl E. (1977) Cartesian meditations. Kluwer Academic Publisher, Dordrecht.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Isayeva N. (1993) Shankara and Indian philosophy. Sri Satguru Publications, Delhi.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
John of the Crosss (2003) Dark night of the soul. Dover publications, New York.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Jung C. G. (1962) Seven sermons to the dead. In: Memories, dreams, reflections. Edited by Aniela Jaffe. Translated by Richard & Clara Winston. Vintage Books, New York. Originally published in 1916.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Krippendorff K. (1991) Stepping stones towards a constructivist epistemology for mass-communication. Unpublished manuscript prepared for presentation to the annual meeting of the Deutsche Gesellschaft für Publizistik und Kommunikationswissenschaft in Bamberg, Germany, 8–10 May 1991, 32 pages.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Kuhn T. (1970) The structure of scientific revolutions. Second Edition. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Lorenz K. (1982) Kant’s doctrine of the a priori in the light of contemporary biology. In: Plotkin H. C. (ed.) Learning, development and culture. John Wiley, Chichester: 121–143. Originally published as: Lorenz K. (1941) Kants Lehre vom Apriorischen im Lichte gegenwärtiger Biologie. Blätter für Deutsche Philosophie 15: 94–125.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Mach E. (1984) The analysis of sensations and the relation of the physical to the psychical. Translated by C. M. Williams. Open Court, La Salle. Originally published in 1896.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Maturana H. (1981) Autopoiesis. In: Zeleny M. (ed.) Autopoiesis: A theory of living organization. North Holland, New York: 21–30.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Maturana H. (1988) Reality: The search for objectivity, or the quest for a compelling argument. The Irish Journal of Psychology 9(1): 25–82.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Maturana H. (2000) The nature of the laws of nature. Yearbook Edition of Systems Research and Behavioral Science, Systems Research 17(5): 459–468.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Merleau-Ponty M. (2005) Phenomenology of perception. Routledge, London. Originally published in French as: Merleau-Ponty M. (1945) Phenomenologie de la perception. Callimard, Paris.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Nargajuna (1995) The fundamental wisdom of the middle way. Translated and commented by Jay L. Garfield. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Oluffa Pedersen E. & Toft P. (2004) Positivisme: Erfaringsbaseret viden formuleret i en logisk sprogramme. In: Fuglsang L. & Bitsch Olsen P. (eds.) Videnskabsteori i samfundsvidenskaberne. Roskilde Universitetsforlag, Copenhagen: 55–77.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Peirce C. S. (1994) CP: The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Electronic edition reproducing Past Masters. Hartshorne C. & Weiss P. (eds.) (1931–1935) Vols. I-VI. Harvard University Press, Cambridge; Burks A. (ed.) (1958) Vols. VII–VIII. Harvard University Press, Cambridge. Intelex Corporation, Charlottesville. All quotes refer to Peirce’s Collected Papers (1994) abbreviated as “CP.”
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Popper K. (1972) Objective knowledge: An evolutionary approach. The Clarendon Press, Oxford.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Sharma C. (2009) A critical survey of Indian philosophy. Motilal Banarsidass, Delhi.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Spencer-Brown G. (as James Keys) (1974) Only two can play this game. Bantam Books, New York.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Steuchius Eugubinus A. (1972) De perenni philosophia, Libri X. Paris. Johnson Reprint, New York. Originally published in 1540 in Paris.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Wittgenstein L. (2001) Philosophical investigations. Blackwell Publishing, Oxford. Originally published in 1953.
▸︎ Google︎ Scholar
Comments: 0
To stay informed about comments to this publication and post comments yourself, please log in first.